I’ve been very satisfied with the progress I’ve made on my
reading list thanks to this blog, if only because I finally finished Brothers Karamazov. Alas, this post documents
a rare failure: I gave up on Plotinus’ inscrutable Enneads. It came in waves. When I got my copy, I set out to read it
in its entirety. Then I noticed that the allegedly abridged version was still
over 600 pages in 8-point font. Somewhat disillusioned, I persisted and got
through the first two books. (“Ennead” comes from the Greek word for “nine,”
and stands for the fact that the treatise is made up of six books, each of
which has nine chapters or sections.) It was incredibly dense, but I resigned
myself to not understanding all of it, and I still managed to get a good deal
out of it.
Then, slowly, my will faltered more and more. The third book
took over a week, and by the time I began the fourth, I had started to Google
which sections I could skim, and then which sections I could skip altogether.
Even getting through those sections was difficult, though, and in the middle of
book four, I admitted defeat.
Plotinus is an incredibly challenging read for two reasons.
The first is his style. My best approximation is that he reads like Heidegger
if Heidegger had been translated from a dead language. He has the same penchant
for inventing terminology (“All-Soul,” “Real-Existent,” and other doubly
capitalized, hyphenated words) that describes esoteric concepts and is never
properly defined to begin with. The second is the translation. Penguin Classics
went with a translation by Stephen MacKenna, who translated Plotinus in the
early twentieth century. Translations from that long ago are usually difficult
enough without the added burden of translating someone as inscrutable as
Plotinus. Though his translation is highly praised (George Steiner called it
one of the great achievements in translation of the twentieth century), it may
be better read for culture than understanding.
Despite all this, Plotinus is worth reading. If nothing
else, his influence is considerable: his thought allowed Augustine to reconcile
important ideas about God and he thereby exerted a profound influence on modern
Christian theology. Dillon, the editor, points out that Plotinus’ notion of the
“we” prefigured Freud’s “ego,” but this feels tacked on, like when they said
Epictetus prefigured modern neuropsychology.)
Soul
Let’s begin where Plotinus does: with the soul. As a neo-Platonist,
Plotinus derives much of his philosophy from close readings and interpolations
of Plato’s dialogues, especially the Timaeus,
but this is not to say that he keeps his distance from other philosophers.
Often, he reads quite like a Stoic, which seems to be popular in late
Antiquity, and in his descriptions of the Soul, he sounds awfully Aristotelian:
the soul and the body are connected, but like the “axe-form on iron” – things
happen to the iron of the axe, not to the form it takes. “The permeating soul
might remain entirely untouched by what affects the body – as light goes always
free of all its floods.”
What is the business of the soul then? Plotinus gives us a
roadmap. There is, at bottom, the ‘Ours,’ the basic couplement of soul and
body. Through sensations, we are able to discern impressions (a Stoic concept),
which “are already Intelligibles” that need to be unlocked, in some sense, by
the soul. Once the soul has translated these impressions into Intelligibles,
they become connected to Ideal-Forms; from knowledge of Ideal-Forms, we have
what gives us the “peculiar” We, so called, I think, because it, like the Ours,
is a couplement of body and soul. (It is interesting to note that “We” has also
been translated as “personality.”) To reiterate:
Ours –> Sensations –> Impressions –> Intelligibles
–> Ideal-Forms –> We
The first three are the domain of our body – that is, our
five ordinary senses – and the final three, of our soul. Says Plotinus: “Thus
assuredly Sense-Perception, Discursive-Reasoning, and all our ordinary
mentation are foreign to the Soul: for sensation is a receiving – whether of an
Ideal-Form or of a bodily affection – and reasoning and all ordinary mental
action deal with sensation.”
Trinity
The Soul, then, is our connection to the world of
Intelligibles, of Ideal-Forms. If the Soul is the means by which the animate
turns impressions into Intelligibles, where does it come from?
There is, primally, the One, what all Forms are, in their essence. If it helps, we can relate the One to
God, although Plotinus would probably spit at us for doing so. Everything is the One, because the One is what all
things, material and immaterial, come from. However, those “things” are not
created by some action of the One, for action would imply change and the One is
incapable of change (like Republicans, hey-o!). Rather, everything is an
“emanation” from the one, a byproduct necessitated by the very existence of the
One.
The primary emanation of the One is the Intellect, which is
the locus of the spectrum of all Forms; all things are united in the One, but
each also has an identity. The Intellect maintains something of a “catalog” of
Forms, allowing for the possibility of “equality”: thus, we can say that
something is both three-dimensional
and solid because the two distinct concepts are connected by this Intellect
identifying each with each. Without the Intellect, predication is impossible. The
Intellect (here’s where it gets really screwy) is in eternal contemplation of
the One, analogous to Plato’s Demiurge.
The Intellect, being an emanation of the One and hence “the
same as” the One (again, it is helpful to think of the Christian Trinity, where
the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are distinct and yet the same), must also have
an emanation. That emanation we identify as the Soul. Everything, from animals
to plants, has a soul, because everything is an emanation from the One, but the
highest action of the Soul is in contemplation of the Intellect, which is the
only way that the One can even remotely be reached. Only people are capable of
Intellection.
I should take a moment to say that I don’t know how accurate
all of that was. It was pieced together from the text, the introduction, and
the extraordinarily helpful Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. If anyone has
read Plotinus (doubtful) and can correct or verify any of that, it would be
most appreciated.
That is Plotinus’ triad, the sum of his mystical beliefs and
the foundation upon which the rest of his philosophy is built. It is difficult
not to see echoes of this in the Christian Trinity, but I’ll save that
discussion for a future post on Augustine.
Ethics and Aesthetics
Having explained the foundation of his theory, Plotinus moves on to its applications. One remarkable feature of the Enneads is the way that Plotinus is able to knit together far-flung areas of philosophy, such as ethics and aesthetics as we will soon see, with his abstract metaphysics.
For example, order is of great importance because it is a reflection of the Intellectual-Principle in the material world. Everything that we consider ordered possesses order only through imitation of the original Order, and by contemplating ordered things, we are actually contemplating the Intellectual-Principle and drawing ourselves closer to the One. It is important, then, for us to direct our Souls toward contemplation of the Intellectual-Principle: we must view something that is beautiful as "not some one shape of beauty but the All-Beauty, the Absolute Beauty;
and the truths of philosophy must be implanted in him to lead him to faith in
that which, unknowing it, he possesses within himself." (We possess the knowledge within ourselves because we are all emanations of the One.)
So, we've concluded that order is an “inner idea stamped upon the mass of exterior matter.” This means that there are certain things we must seek out: virtue, for example. Virtue, both moral and civic, is important to Plotinus because it brings “bound and measure to our desires and to our entire sensibility.” That which is bounded -- the One is infinitely bounded and unified -- is always, by definition, preferable to the boundless. Virtue, then, is a way of aligning our Souls with Intellection. Beauty is the same: "He must be led to the Beauty that manifests itself through these forms
[tone, rhythm, design; in essence, through worldly things]; he must be shown
that what ravished him was no other than the Harmony of the Intellectual world
and the Beauty in that sphere."
The Nature of Evil
If order, limit, and bound are characteristics of the One and hence of the Good, it is not surprising that evil is defined as “Undetermination-Absolute, some Absolute Formlessness…the kind whose
place is below all the patterns, forms, shapes, measurements, and limits.” Included in this limitlessness is matter, which is also inherently evil. (This is a Gnostic idea, although Plotinus hated the Gnostics for reasons I couldn't figure out.)
He explains: “The bodily Kind, in that it partakes of Matter, is an evil
thing. What form is in bodies is an untrue form: they are without life: by
their own natural disorderly movement they make away with each other; they are
hindrances to the Soul in its proper Act; in their ceaseless flux they are
always slipping away from Being.” That last bit sounds an awful lot like
entropy. Can you tell us more, Plotinus?
“The Measurelessness is
evil primarily; whatever, either by resemblance or participation, exists in the
state of unmeasured, is evil secondarily.” I think we get the idea. Simplicity is good, complexity is evil. Fastidiousness is good, changeability
is evil. I always like to bring this back to Othello: Iago’s formlessness, Othello’s Classical heroism. We can
also recall in Kafka’s The Castle, K.
is a land-surveyor, in charge of delimiting boundaries. This all works out very
nicely. We are to align our Souls with Intellect and not with our bodies
because bodies are matter and matter is evil.
If we are not concerned with matter, then we need not fear
evil. This is a Stoic argument. But Plotinus goes a step
further. If we are not distressed by the possibility of evil, then why
be distressed by actual evil? “What then, we ask, if he had died without
witnessing the wrong [one's daughters and daughters-in-law dragged away to
captivity]? Could he have quitted the world in the calm conviction that nothing
of all this could happen? He must be very shallow. Can he fail to see that it
is possible for such calamities to overtake his household, and does he cease to
be a happy man for the knowledge of what may occur? In the knowledge of the
possibility he may be at ease; as, too, when the evil has come about.” This fits in nicely with the classical argument for courage: we should not be cowardly
because cowardice is fear of something that has not yet happened. If we are
brave then we will not fear what has not yet happened; if we do not fear evil
that has not yet happened, we will also not fear that has happened.
The Evil of Nature
A discussion of evil leads easily into the question of
theodicy. Evil, as we have seen, is not the caused by the One, as if it had
engendered it in some way: the One, to reiterate, does not “act” in any sense of the
word. Evil, instead, arises by necessity, as a byproduct of the nature of the
One: just as the Intellect and the Soul emanate from the One, so too does evil
come about because the emanation is not limitless (if it were, it would be
evil). Think of this as a flashlight. A flashlight illuminates the area around
it, but it is not the intention of the flashlight to create darkness or even to
leave darkness as it is. Rather, the flashlight is limited in its capacity;
light can only stretch so far. This is pretty standard reasoning when it comes
to theodicy, and I don’t think it originated from Plotinus.
In his own words: “We are like people ignorant of painting
who complain that the colours are not beautiful everywhere in the picture: but
the Artist has laid on the appropriate tint to every spot… Again, we are
censuring a drama because the persons are not all heroes.” Evil arises not
through carelessness on the part of the One, but through necessity.
This necessity is interesting to me, particularly because of the sense of coexistence and unity inherent in it. Here’s Plotinus again: “All things, as they
rise from a unity [the One], come back to unity by a sheer need of nature; differences
unfold themselves, contraries are produced, but all is drawn into one organized
system by the unity at the source.”
Eternity
Plotinus draws an interesting distinction between time and
eternity. The usual notion of eternity is infinite linear time (or at least
that’s how I always thought of it), but he distinguishes it in a different
way: “We know it as a Life changelessly motionless and ever holding the
Universal content in actual presence; not this now and now that other, but
always all." That is, eternity is not infinite time, but all of time at the
same instant, in the same place. Time is an imperfect image of the Real Being,
eternity, and so in imitating eternity, it produces a discursive level of being
(not my phrasing), where one thing follows another. Cause and effect are illusory
because in the Real Being, there is no “this now and now that other.” This
should make us think of two things: the distinction between the third
and fourth dimensions (I like to reference this video), and the Tralfamadorians in Vonnegut’s Slaughterhouse-Five.
Also, we can (Plotinus does not) equate eternity with repose: since one thing
does not follow another, there is rest.
Free Will
“Again, if all our action is determined by a natural
process, how can the distinction be maintained between behaviour in accordance
with nature and behaviour in conflict with it? And what becomes of blasphemy
against the divine? The blasphemer is made what he is: a dramatist has written
a part insulting and maligning himself and given it to an actor to play.”
Plotinus raises the question of free will – if someone deity
has predetermined the actions of every person at every time, how can a
blasphemer be held accountable for his insolence? He answers himself, to a degree,
later on: “The act of the libertine is not done by Providence or in accordance
with Providence; neither is the action of the good done by Providence – it is
done by the man – but it is done in accordance with Providence, for it is an
act consonant with the Reason-Principle. Thus a patient following his treatment
is himself an agent and yet is acting in accordance with the doctor’s method
inspired by the art concerned with the causes of health and sickness: what one
does against the laws of health is one’s act, but an act conflicting with the
Providence of medicine.”
Nature, in the sense of that which is preordained, perhaps
does not exist, then, as something inalterable, but as a prescription like that
of a doctor. Many philosophers repeat the adage that God (or the gods) don’t
subject us to more than we can bear, so if perhaps things seem unbearable at
times, it is only because we have wandered off the path that is consonant with
nature.
That which is done in accordance with the good – that is,
with eyes toward the Intellectual-Principle – can only ever be consonant with
the flow of nature, and that which is not is never so. This is a way of
reconciling free will with predestination. The path is determined, but we are
free to wander: there are limitless options from which we may choose, but there
is only one correct way, that of the good. Just as a doctor may prescribe a
drug with the knowledge that his patient will toss the script away, so too is
predestination compatible with the “act of the libertine.”
Stray Observations
- In case all of the above was too straightforward, here’s one of my favorite impenetrable sentences from the book: “When the Intellect is in upward orientation that (lower part of it) which contains (or, corresponds to) the life of the Soul, is, so to speak, flung down again…” Can you imagine what that looks like in Greek?
- There’s a nice analogy of a musician that I chose not to discuss because it’s very similar to a lot of what’s already been said in previous posts, but I’ll quote it here. “When the lyre fails him, [the musician] will change it, or will give up lyre and lyring, as having another craft now, one that needs no lyre, and then he will let it rest unregarded at this side while he sings on without an instrument. But it was not idly that the instrument was given him in the beginning: he has found it useful until now, many a time."
- “Feelings are not states; they are action upon experience, action accompanied by judgement.” State would imply something fixed: the state of the weather currently is “rainy,” and it must be rainy until a different state replaces it. Calling it action gives agency to the individual rather than some inherent quality of being. As Iago says, “’Tis in ourselves that we are thus or thus."
- If anyone out there has been inspired to read Plotinus, I’d give the Loeb Library editions a go. They’re expensive, but the translation is much more recent, which may help.
No comments:
Post a Comment